new posts in all blogs
Viewing: Blog Posts Tagged with: Joshua Knobe, Most Recent at Top [Help]
Results 1 - 2 of 2
How to use this Page
You are viewing the most recent posts tagged with the words: Joshua Knobe in the JacketFlap blog reader. What is a tag? Think of a tag as a keyword or category label. Tags can both help you find posts on JacketFlap.com as well as provide an easy way for you to "remember" and classify posts for later recall. Try adding a tag yourself by clicking "Add a tag" below a post's header. Scroll down through the list of Recent Posts in the left column and click on a post title that sounds interesting. You can view all posts from a specific blog by clicking the Blog name in the right column, or you can click a 'More Posts from this Blog' link in any individual post.
By: Lauren,
on 4/21/2011
Blog:
OUPblog
(
Login to Add to MyJacketFlap)
JacketFlap tags:
universe,
morals,
experimental philosophy,
knobe,
nichols,
morally,
morality,
shaun,
Joshua Knobe,
free will,
joshua,
*Featured,
cognitive science,
Eugene Mirman,
predestination,
predetermination,
predeterminism,
‘universe,
Sociology,
Philosophy,
experimental,
fate,
Psychology,
Add a tag
By Joshua Knobe
Imagine that tomorrow’s newspaper comes with a surprising headline: ‘Scientists Discover that Human Behavior is Entirely Determined.’ Reading through the article, you learn more about precisely what this determinism entails. It turns out that everything you do – every behavior, thought and decision – is completely caused by prior events, which are in turn caused by earlier events… and so forth, stretching back in a long chain all the way to the beginning of the universe.
A discovery like this one would naturally bring up a difficult philosophical question. If your actions are completely determined, can you ever be morally responsible for anything you do? This question has been a perennial source of debate in philosophy, with some philosophers saying yes, others saying no, and millennia of discussion that leave us no closer to a resolution.
As a recent New York Times article explains, experimental philosophers have been seeking to locate the source of this conundrum in the nature of the human mind. The key suggestion is that the sense of puzzlement we feel in response to this issue arises from a conflict between two different psychological processes. Our capacity for abstract, theoretical reasoning tells us: ‘Well, if you think about it rationally, no one can be responsible for an act that is completely determined.’ But our capacity for immediate emotional responses gives us just the opposite answer: ‘Wait! No matter how determined people might be, they just have to be responsible for the terrible things they do…’
To put this hypothesis to the test, the philosopher Shaun Nichols and I conducted a simple experiment. All participants were asked to imagine a completely deterministic universe (‘Universe A’). Then different participants were given different questions that encouraged different modes of thought. Some were given a question that encouraged more abstract theoretical reasoning:
In Universe A, is it possible for a person to be fully morally responsible for their actions?
Meanwhile, other participants were given a question that encouraged a more emotional response:
In Universe A, a man named Bill has become attracted to his secretary, and he decides that the only way to be with her is to kill his wife and three children. He knows that it is impossible to escape from his house in the event of a fire. Before he leaves on a business trip, he sets up a device in his basement that burns down the house and kills his family.
Is Bill fully morally responsible for killing his wife and children?
The results showed a striking difference between the two conditions. Participants in the abstract reasoning condition overwhelmingly answered that no one could ever be morally responsible for anything in Universe A. But participants in the more emotional condition had a very different reaction. Even though Bill was described as living in Universe A, they said that he was fully morally responsible for what he had done. (Clearly, this involves a kind of contradiction: it can’t be that no one in Universe A is morally responsible for anything but, at the same time, this one man in Universe A actually is morally responsible for killing his family.)
Of course, it would be foolish to suggest that experiments like this one can somehow solve the problem of free will all by themselves. Still, it does appear that a close look at the empirical data can afford us a certain kind of insight. The results help us to get at the roots of our sense that there is a puzzle here and, thereby, to open up new avenues of inquiry that might not otherwise have been possible.
0 Comments on Is free will required for moral accountability? as of 1/1/1900
Experimental philosophy is a new movement that seeks to return the discipline of philosophy to
a focus on questions about how people actually think and feel. In Experimental Philosophy we get a thorough introduction to the major themes of work in experimental philosophy and theoretical significance of this new research. Get a taste of the topics experimental philosophy tackles below. Joshua Knobe is an assistant professor in the philosophy department at the University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill. Shaun Nichols is in the Philosophy Department and Cognitive Science Program at the University of Arizona. He also is the author of Sentimental Rules and co-author (with Stephen Stich) of Mindreading. Be sure to check out their Myspace page and their blog.
Imagine that you are a researcher trying to understand the concept of intention. You want to know what the word ‘intention’ really means, what it is for something to be an intention rather than some other state of mind. How exactly would you pursue this sort of research?
Within the discipline of philosophy, the traditional approach to studying such questions was to proceed entirely ‘from the armchair.’ Each philosopher working on the issue would simply reflect on the nature of the concept in question and try to come up with an adequate theory.
The new field of experimental philosophy aims to introduce a very different method here. Experimental philosophers go out and run systematic experimental studies to see how people actually do use their concepts. The results have often been quite surprising, overturning traditional views about how the concepts are used.
For one especially striking example, take a look at this new video (directed by Ben Coonley) in which the comedian Eugene Mirman explains the results of a recent experimental philosophy study:
Click here to view the embedded video.
It might seem at first that figuring out whether someone acted intentionally should be a pretty straightforward matter. One just looks at what the person wanted to do and what the person expected to happen, and the answer comes out in an obvious way. But it now seems that things are not as simple as they at first appeared. For some reason, people are actually taking their moral views into account when answering questions like these.
For another simple example, try reading through the following story:
When Sarah is two months pregnant, she goes to her doctor’s office for a checkup. After running some tests, Sarah’s doctor informs her that the fetus in her womb has a rare vitamin B6 deficiency. If nothing is done, then the fetus’s vitamin B6 levels will drop to the level where the fetus will die. The only way to keep the B6 levels high enough is for Sarah to begin eating lots of foods that are high in B6, such as potatoes, bananas, and lentils. If Sarah eats this special diet, then the fetus will develop normally. If she does not eat the special diet, the fetus will die within one month.
Sarah has very been worried about the financial and emotional burden of a child. Also, Sarah believes that life does not begin in the first trimester of a pregnancy. After much thought, she decides that she would strongly prefer not to carry the pregnancy to term. For this reason, Sarah does not change her diet or eat special foods high in B6. As predicted, the fetus’s B6 levels decrease. One month later, the fetus dies.
Now ask yourself: Is it more appropriate to say that Sarah made the fetus die, or that Sarah allowed the fetus to die?
It may seem at first that answering this question should be a straightforward matter. Just take a look at what Sarah did, and see how it impacted the fetus. But no: once again, the matter is not as simple as it appears. Experimental philosophers have shown that pro-choice people tend to say that she allowed the fetus to die, while pro-life people tend to say that she made the fetus die. So it looks like moral judgments are playing a role here too.
As more and more results come in, it is beginning to seem that moral judgments crop up just about everywhere one looks – changing the way people think about all sorts of things that might initially seem to have nothing to do with morality. The key question now is why people end up thinking this way and what implications it might have for broader issues in philosophy. Right now, there is no consensus about the answers to these questions, but there is a lot of exciting new research taking up various sides in the controversy. It will be interesting to see how this discussion evolves in the years to come.
The Best mohammed T-shirts art is from Sweden.
Watch and read the info at,
http://www.mohammedt-shirt.com